Wellorderings
I've already told you what is an ordering, but let me give a quick reminder. A (strict) ordering on some set \(X\) is a a binary relation, usually denoted by some variation on the symbol \(<\), which is
- irreflexive, that is for all \(x\in X\), it is not the case that \(x<x\),
- transitive, that is for all \(x,y,z\in X\), if \(x<y\) and \(y<z\), then \(x<z\).
One very important example is the standard ordering on natural numbers. In that case, we have that \(X=\omega\) and \(<=\in\). To understand the second thing, recall that in Set Theory, natural numbers are coded as \(0=\emptyset\), \(1=\{0\}\), \(2=\{0,1\}\), \(3=\{0,1,2\}\), and so on. Hence, for example, \(1<3\) because
\[1\in \{0,1,2\}=3.\]
In addition to the irreflexivity and transitivity, this relation satisfies some other important properties. One of them is being
- total, that is for all \(x,y\in X\), one of the options is true: \(x<y\) or \(x=y\) or \(x>y\).
The orderings which are total are called total orderings or even cooler, linear orderings.
The properties that I listed so far are probably already familiar to you. In addition to them, the standard ordering of natural numbers satisfies a wirder property which is equivalent to the already mentioned principle of the induction. To phrase is properly, let me introduce some terminology. If \(Y\) is a subset of \(X\) and if \(y\) is an element of \(X\), then \(y\) is said to be the minimum of \(Y\) if two conditions are met: (1) \(y\) is an element of \(Y\) and (2) every other element of \(Y\) is bigger than \(y\). I said "the" minimum because if it exists, then it is unique: if we had two minima \(y_0\) and \(y_1\), then the second property would give that both \(y_0< y_1\) and \(y_1<y_0\), which with the transitivity would imply that \(y_0<y_0\), and contradict the irreflexivity! Of course, the minimum might not exist, but I'll illustrate that a bit later.
For now, let us come back to the case \(X=\omega\) and \(<=\in\). Here, the empty set does not have a minimum (because nothing belongs to it!), but all other subsets of \(\omega\) do have a minimum! This is that additional property equivalent to the induction. We say that a linear ordering is a wellordering if every non-empty subset has a minimum. Thus, the ordering of natural numbers is a wellordering. Other examples of wellorderings are the individual natural numbers, say \(X=5\) and \(<=\in\). In this case, every subset of \(5\) is also a subset of \(\omega\), because
\[5=\{0,1,2,3,4\}\subseteq\{0,1,2,3,4,5,6,\dots\}=\omega.\]
Then every such subset has a minimum since that's true for subsets of \(\omega\).
An example of a wellordering other than a natural number or \(\omega\) is the set
\[\omega\cup\{\omega\}=\{0,1,2,3,4,\dots, 1002345,\dots, \omega\},\]
again ordered by \(\in\). This ordering is called \(\omega+1\), but more on that later. Of coure, you are probably curious about linear orderings which are no wellorderings. First, we also have the notion of a maximum: \(y\in X\) is the maximum of \(Y\subseteq X\) if (1) \(y\in Y\) and (2) every other element of \(Y\) is smaller than \(y\). In the case of natural numbers, the subset \(Y:=\omega\) does not have a maximum! Now, to get an example of an ordering without a minimum we just need to transform maxima into minima. Let \(<^*\) be the ordering on \(\omega\) obtained by "turning around" the standard ordering, that is we say that \(m<^* n\) if and only if \(m>n\). Then the ordering \((\omega,<^*)\) does not have a minimum!
Comments
Post a Comment