Wellorderings

I've already told you what is an ordering, but let me give a quick reminder. A (strict) ordering on some set X is a a binary relation, usually denoted by some variation on the symbol <, which is 

  • irreflexive, that is for all xX, it is not the case that x<x,
  • transitive, that is for all x,y,zX, if x<y and y<z, then x<z.
One very important example is the standard ordering on natural numbers. In that case, we have that X=ω and <=∈. To understand the second thing, recall that in Set Theory, natural numbers are coded as 0=, 1={0}, 2={0,1}, 3={0,1,2}, and so on. Hence, for example, 1<3 because
1{0,1,2}=3.
In addition to the irreflexivity and transitivity, this relation satisfies some other important properties. One of them is being
  • total, that is for all x,yX, one of the options is true: x<y or x=y or x>y.
The orderings which are total are called total orderings or even cooler, linear orderings. 

The properties that I listed so far are probably already familiar to you. In addition to them, the standard ordering of natural numbers satisfies a wirder property which is equivalent to the already mentioned principle of the induction. To phrase is properly, let me introduce some terminology. If Y is a subset of X and if y is an element of X, then y is said to be the minimum of Y if two conditions are met: (1) y is an element of Y and (2) every other element of Y is bigger than y. I said "the" minimum because if it exists, then it is unique: if we had two minima y0 and y1, then the second property would give that both y0<y1 and y1<y0,  which with the transitivity would imply that y0<y0, and contradict the irreflexivity! Of course, the minimum might not exist, but I'll illustrate that a bit later.

For now, let us come back to the case X=ω and <=∈. Here, the empty set does not have a minimum (because nothing belongs to it!), but all other subsets of ω do have a minimum! This is that additional property equivalent to the induction. We say that a linear ordering is a wellordering if every non-empty subset has a minimum. Thus, the ordering of natural numbers is a wellordering. Other examples of wellorderings are the individual natural numbers, say X=5 and <=∈. In this case, every subset of 5 is also a subset of ω, because
5={0,1,2,3,4}{0,1,2,3,4,5,6,}=ω.
Then every such subset has a minimum since that's true for subsets of ω.

An example of a wellordering other than a natural number or ω is the set
ω{ω}={0,1,2,3,4,,1002345,,ω},
again ordered by . This ordering is called ω+1, but more on that later. Of coure, you are probably curious about linear orderings which are no wellorderings. First, we also have the notion of a maximum: yX is the maximum of YX if (1) yY and (2) every other element of Y is smaller than y. In the case of natural numbers, the subset Y:=ω does not have a maximum! Now, to get an example of an ordering without a minimum we just need to transform maxima into minima. Let < be the ordering on ω obtained by "turning around" the standard ordering, that is we say that m<n if and only if m>n. Then the ordering (ω,<) does not have a minimum!

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Axiom of Powerset

Relations